Obsolete Free-Market Metaphors
“There is no such thing as society”.
So said Mrs Thatcher. She apparently meant that
“society” can be seen only as an abstraction
or cultural metaphor. Adherents of free-market
economics have often expressed a dislike of
terms like “society” and “social concern”. The
market system has traditionally had an individualistic
bias its central premise is that the
market registers choices made by separate, sovereign
individuals who freely consume for themselves.
If every economic effect is seen
to result from the free choices of autonomous,
atomistic consumers and entrepreneurs, then
“society” will be viewed as a nebulous metaphor
with little economic relevance. Those who blame
their financial problems on an aspect of “society”
are unlikely to receive any sympathy from free-marketeers.
Ironically, critics of the competitive
market system would argue that “free market”
is itself a metaphor, an idealised abstraction
whose central premise fails to take into account
the vast array of social factors affecting human
motivation and behaviour. For instance, social
phenomena such as advertising, state education
and the mass media inevitably tend to influence
the value systems which determine what individual
consumers will buy. The notion of a ‘totally
rational’ individual, completely immune from
‘social’ influences, is naive. And contrary
to free-market thinking, ‘society’ has aspects
which can’t be explained or predicted in terms
of the rational choices made by its individual
constituents. To view a complex phenomenon like
a human society as no more than the sum of its
parts is to subscribe to a kind of reductionism
belonging to the 18th century (which was when
classical free-market economic theory originated).
Is free-market philosophy
“perhaps the world’s leading example of cultural
bias and historical circumstance disguised as
a principal of science”?
Only Britain and the USA put the
free-market idea of individual self-interest
so far above notions of ‘social concern’. The
European capitalist model is more ‘communal’
in its emphasis, as reflected, for instance,
by the Social Chapter of the Maastricht treaty.
Meanwhile, Japan possibly the most economically
successful of all capitalist nations
has a more communitarian model than even Europe.
To the Japanese, the main purpose of business
is to benefit society.
‘Communal’ does not infer communism
or statism, but merely cultural perspectives
which recognise that wealth-creation may not
be an entirely individualistic pursuit.
Of course, there are good reasons
for the Anglo-American belief that economic
self-interest must take precedence over social
concern. Adam Smith observed that merchants
acting from selfish motivations tended to produce
more of public value than those motivated by
benevolence towards society. The reasons for
this are easy enough to follow self-interest
fuels competitiveness and, according to classical
economists, shifting resources to those who
compete successfully and away from those who
compete badly is a process which promotes economic
growth, thus benefiting everyone.
But just as the metaphors of, say,
Freudian psychology mirror the technology of
the times (eg hydraulic build-up of pressure,
letting off steam, etc), classical economic
metaphors reflect the Newtonian mechanical view
of the world. There is an almost mathematical
satisfaction to be gained from understanding
the classical economic notion of ‘supply and
demand’, as if predicting economic effects is
a simple problem of physical mechanics. The
market ‘mechanism’ is even regarded as a sort
of universal scientific law by many economists
and business people.
Professor Paul Ormerod, of the
Henley Centre forecasting organisation, has
pointed out that Western economic theory has
been conspicuously unsuccessful at making the
kind of accurate predictions you would expect
from a scientific discipline. He goes as far
as saying that little in standard economics
texts is known to be true, and that orthodox
economics still has no effective answer for
basic problems such as unemployment.
Is the classical view
of the effectiveness of self-interest within a
‘free market’ a universal law or just a cultural
prejudice favouring the greedy and predatory?
So is the classical view of the
effectiveness of self-interest within a ‘free
market’ a universal law or just a cultural prejudice
favouring the greedy and predatory? In their
book, The Seven Cultures of Capitalism,
Charles Hampden-Turner and Fons Trompenaars
describe Adam Smith’s doctrine of self-interest
as “perhaps the world’s leading example of cultural
bias and historical circumstance disguised as
a principal of science”. They argue that market
forces depend on specific cultural contexts
and shouldn’t be seen to act in an impersonal,
universal way the market shouldn’t be
revered as a neutral arbiter ‘out there’. Their
book is rich in examples which contradict the
fundamental assumptions of mainstream economics.
Sweden, for example, has been something
of an enigma to classical economists. A strong
social democratic welfare state, with substantial
government control moderating economic fluctuations,
has put Sweden in the “soft” category of capitalism
(but with very little industry nationalised,
it is outside the “socialist” categorisation).
If business is necessarily a ruthless struggle
between self-interested competitors, how did
Sweden’s “softness” (social equality, humanitarianism,
welfare and environmental concern) lead to such
a strong economy? Sweden has had one of the
world’s highest standards of living (in 1992
GDP per person was $12,000 higher than in the
UK), and working conditions and labour-management
relations have generally been excellent. Economists
rationalised that Sweden was a small, insulated
exception to universally harsh economic laws,
but, in fact, since the late nineteenth century
Sweden has been a world economy highly exposed
to international trends.
Similarly, in Germany, Holland
and Japan, benevolence towards ‘society’ (as
expressed towards employees, customers and local
communities) is very much part of their economic
strategies, rather than simply a hoped-for effect
of the market mechanism. This tendency hasn’t
harmed the economic growth of these countries
(from 1979 to 1991, manufacturing grew by 33.3%
in Germany and 60.4% in Japan, compared with
4.9% in Britain. Also, GDP per capita in Britain
continued to lose comparative advantage with
these countries during this period).
Britain’s leading companies are
extremely profitable, and, in fact, competitiveness
tends to be measured here solely by the level
of profit extracted. Obsession with profit,
however, is not a common factor in successful
economies. In Germany the pursuit of technical
excellence and service to society through producing
quality products is more valued than profit
making. The Japanese see capitalism as a system
in which communities serve customers, rather
than one in which individuals compete to extract
profits profitability is the means, not
the end. With the emphasis less on the short-term
profits of the individual owner/shareholder,
there is a degree of co-operative activity in
German and Japanese industry which is quite
alien to the British and American “lean and
mean” approach.
From the western perspective of
analytical either/or logic, we must choose
either co-operation or competition we
can’t have both at the same time. Or, to put
it in terms of the mechanistic metaphor, we
can’t push and pull simultaneously. So, following
classical economics, we choose competition and
get rid of co-operation. However, using metaphors
of “integrated wholes” (eg “organic”, “cybernetic”
or “structured network” models), much of European
and Japanese industry has learnt how to reconcile
co-operation with competition. This is an especially
important trend in the area of high technology.
But what does reconciling co-operation
and competition mean in practice? The question
we should probably ask is: What is the thing
that competes? an individual, a company,
an industry, or a nation? Early on in the development
of capitalism, individuals competed with other
individuals, then, later, competition was largely
between companies whose employees co-operated
(although fierce competition is still encouraged
between individual employees in the UK and US).
Japan has spread the level of co-operation
further still, in the keiretsu (a co-operative
conglomerate), whose divisional companies co-operate
and share technological knowledge and resources
(in British and American conglomerates, the
divisions compete with each other for the funding
of the holding company, and share nothing).
Thus, the development of capitalism may be seen
as “..a function of evolving co-operation, which
spreads outward, pushing competition to its
own boundaries” (The Seven Cultures of Capitalism).
In order to compete successfully
at the national level, European nations have
largely adopted the internally co-operative
approach, in contrast with the UK, where the
political strategy has been to increase internal
competition. The UK approach derives from a
belief in the universal nature of the
market mechanism ie the conviction that
all-out competition will work at all
levels.
Describing economic progress in
terms of evolving co-operation, rather than
ruthless self-interested competition, may have
important benefits, particularly in knowledge-intensive
markets (eg high technology), where a co-operative
free flow of information throughout a company
(or industry) is likely to prove more effective
than jealous guarding of privileged knowledge
by ambitious individuals. In fact, the information
technology revolution is increasingly leading
to commercial scenarios which the mechanistic
metaphors of classical economics are unable
to deal with.
We often hear politicians
talking piously about the responsibility of individuals
to contribute to the country’s economic success,
but they rarely say what they mean, which is that
people should conform to their definition
of “contribute”.
The metaphors we use to describe
economic success have a flip side that we can’t
easily escape from. If we believe that a competitive
and individualistic (rather than co-operative
and communitarian) approach is the way to succeed,
then it follows that economic failure must
be the fault of individuals who aren’t competing
hard enough, rather than ‘social’ factors (blaming
‘society’ isn’t allowed). We therefore resent
the poor for their lack of individual initiative,
and despise people who blame their problems
on social circumstances.
There is a lot of irony in this.
The emphasis on “success” being solely the individual’s
responsibility fails to take into account the
role of social consensus in defining “success”.
We often hear politicians talking piously about
the responsibility of individuals to contribute
to the country’s economic success, but they
rarely say what they mean, which is that people
should conform to their definition of
“contribute”. ‘Society’ in fact holds us accountable
for not complying with its definition
of our individual responsibilities.
|